To understand Anselm’s argument there are two main thoughts
that we should not at any point forget. The first is who the God is that we are
either affirming or denying. The second is once we know who this God is it
becomes impossible to deny His existence. This entry deals more with the
second, but at the same time the first point is present throughout.
I’ll deal with the first point more directly in a future
post, because we will have to deal with at least two main objections to
Anselm’s argument: 1. This argument defines existence into God; and 2. So we
have to admit there is a God, but none of this says that it is the God of the
Bible. A response to these objections will have to come after we have seen what
the argument is saying. So first we deal with the impossibility of rationally
denying God’s existence.
The main point about the argument is that the one who says,
“There is no God” has to talk about the God that the Bible affirms and that the
believer claims to believe in. That is, by definition it can’t be a different god.
But it is impossible to define that very same God that the Bible is about and
then to have the same definition when you deny His existence. This implies that we ought to know the God of
the Bible better; and that has mostly been the problem when people try to
understand the argument.
The argument goes like this:
We must first establish a definition of God that both the
believer and the unbeliever can agree on. Anselm offers the definition that God
is He “than which a greater cannot be conceived.” The believer and the denier
would have to agree with this definition, because the believer will believe no
less of a deity, and the denier would deny no less of a deity. But when the
denier denies such a God he has to at the same time deny the definition that he
has accepted.
Here’s why. A God that exists is greater in conception than
a God that does not exist. And it is plain that if the denier can conceive of a
being than which a greater cannot be conceived but which does not exist then he can surely conceive of a being than which a
greater cannot be conceived but which does exist. And this one is greater. Thus
the God he is referring to, the one that does not exist, is not as great as the
one he does not refer to, the one that does exist. In saying that He than which
a greater cannot be conceived does not exist the denier is at the same time
admitting that he can conceive of a greater than the God he is denying. So by
definition it is not the same God which the believer believes. Nor is it the
definition that the denier first had to agree to.
Anselm follows this up with a number of the attributes of
God that are commonly called into question when people try to demonstrate the
rationale of denying of God’s existence. The most usual attributes of God
brought forward are God’s perfect justice and His perfect mercy. God cannot
have the one without doing harm to the other, they assert. If God is merciful
to the sinner then He is also being unjust in not punishing sin to its due
requirement; and if God is perfectly just, and all men are sinners, then He
cannot be merciful and so leave behind His justice. But it is clear that these
people can conceive of a God whose justice and mercy do not violate each other,
because the conception of a justice and a mercy that do not violate each other is
greater in wisdom and power. God’s unlimited wisdom and power cannot be so that He is
without power to be just. Nor is His wisdom limited by His justice so that He
does not know how to show mercy. So the
God that they say cannot be both just and merciful is not He than which a
greater cannot be conceived.
The believer right away thinks of Jesus, the God-man taking
the full weight of the punishment for sin upon Himself, so that God could be
perfectly and fully just and at the same time graciously and abundantly
merciful; and he rejoices in such a glorious salvation. We need to pay careful
attention to all that God says about Himself in the Bible, and not just be
comfortable in our own narrow little definitions of who He is. The believer is
always searching out his own errors in his thinking so that the God he believes
in with his whole heart may be glorified in his thoughts as well.
Anselm, of course, is more eloquent in stating the argument
than I am, as well as in defending God’s justice and mercy. I’m trying only to
summarize it in the limited space of this journal entry. All I can do is
summarize it partially; there is more to it than this brief summary.
There is a lot more to discuss that is either directly
addressed or is implied in his argumentation. This is enough, however to see that there are
many, many applications to today’s secular world of God-denial. The most
important application, I think, is to the modern assumption that any notion of
God is only speculation at best, and that no one can prove any religion to be better
and truer than another. All religions have to be seen as equal, and also be equally
true. That, of course, is contradictory. The assumption of “no true religion”
is
exactly equal to “no religion at all”.
As an aside, isn’t it interesting that as you listen to John
Lennon’s song Imagine, and it gets to the part where it says “and no
religion too”, the people that the song is trying to convince are those who
already believe in “no religion” because they steadfastly and firmly hold to
the equality of all religions? It’s speaking to the secularized world. Neither
Lennon nor those he was trying to convince are talking about the same religion
that the Christian believes in. On this point we should agree with Lennon, that
this contradictory and half-witted definition of religion really doesn’t make
sense. Lennon, however, doesn’t come close to critiquing that religion which is
not contradictory.
The non-contradictory conception of religious truth is just
not given a moment’s standing in our modern society, or in the media, or in
governing decisions and policies. Belief in God is allowed, and even protected
by law and by the constitution, but only if it is the God that the deniers deny
and not the God that believers believe. You may believe in your god, just don’t
say he is the One True God, because in today’s society that is intolerant and
unacceptable. That really means that you may freely believe in any god, just
don’t really believe in him.
But belief in God intrinsically involves the exclusion of
any other god as God. So the above view of religious freedom is contradictory,
and Lennon was right to try to imagine it away.
For now let’s just leave out whether this is a proof of
God’s existence. We’ll get back to what Anselm said, but for now let’s just say
that whenever someone says, “There is no God” he just has a different
definition and therefore a different conception of God than the God that the
believer says he believes in. Or, to say it differently, when someone says,
“There is no God” he changes the definition of God, and therefore his
conception of God, from the one that the believer has in mind. The denier of
God’s existence cannot have the same conception of God in his denial of God
that the believer has in his belief in God. He who says there is no God is
really just denying the God of his own conception, not the God that the
believer conceives of.
Do we want it simpler than that? Ok, let’s try this:
whenever someone comes up to you about your belief in God to try to convince
you that there is no God, then you can quite honestly respond to him with, “I
am in full agreement with you.” You may then add: “The god that you say does
not exist I too say does not exist. However, if you want to talk about the God
that I believe in instead, then I must insist that we talk about the same
entity. Can you do that and be honest to it? Because there is one thing that
you cannot honestly say about this God, and that is that He does not exist. Can
we talk about Him, then?”
No comments:
Post a Comment